Is happiness the highest good? (See previous post.) Aristotle says yes because it is the only
good that is an end in itself. Virtue,
like other goods, is a means to the end of happiness. But, is it possible to be virtuous and
unhappy? Further, have you ever heard
someone praised for being happy? We may
be happy for them, but is happiness a praiseworthy achievement? Happiness is a state of being, but virtue is
a trait of character that we find praiseworthy regardless of whether the virtuous
person is happy or not. Which is the
higher good, to be happy and dishonorable or to be virtuous and unhappy?
Virtue ethics focuses on character rather than rules or acts
or consequences. If one develops an
honorable character, one will act ethically.
Motive is more important than consequences. Character is a central element of fiction, and we have considered it in
previous posts on literature and ethics.
Does the character of the lawyer in “Bartleby the Scrivener” (Sept.
2013) merit salvation? Is the character of the bishop in “The Bishop and the Candlesticks”
(Oct. 2013) too good to be true? Can the
character of the soldier in “A Horseman in the Sky” (Nov. 2013) be separated
from his actions? Is Stockmann’s character superior to the townspeople in “An
Enemy of the People” (Nov. 2013)? What exactly is the character of “The Ones
Who Walk Away from Omelas” (Dec. 2013), or, for that matter, of those who don't?
In those cases, we assume we know what constitutes good vs.
bad or strong vs. weak character. Ayn
Rand is an author who puts our conventional views to the test.
In Part III, Chapter VII (“This is John Galt Speaking”) of
her 1957 novel Atlas Shrugged, she presents
a defense of Ethical Egoism, in which virtue is equated with the rational
pursuit of individual happiness without regard for the welfare of others. We are each responsible for our own
happiness, not for others’, and selfishness is a virtue. (See previous post, Sept. 2012.)
As a secular materialist and atheist, Rand explicitly
rejects the Christian ethics of humility, charity, and altruism. Similarly, the notion of “duty” to be found
in deontological ethics is anathema to her since it bases morality on
obligatory principles rather than freely chosen means to one’s own
happiness. She likewise rejects the
Utilitarian ethics of the “greatest happiness for the greatest number.” It is individual happiness that is the greatest
value. She offers her own version of
virtue ethics, replacing such commonly accepted virtues as love, compassion, humility,
generosity, moderation, fairness, reciprocity, self-discipline, gratitude, etc.,
with such characteristics as self-love, radical individualism, and value production. The praiseworthy individual is the “producer”
of value who pursues his or her own happiness and resists the “parasites,
looters, and moochers” who seek to live off the producers. In Rand’s world, the “producers” equate with
owners of property and capital. That these owners produce value off the labor
of workers, who serve as means to the end of the producers’ happiness, utterly
escapes Ayn Rand.
Such a philosophy assumes that we are all equal in our
abilities and opportunities, that suffering is the result of our own failures,
and that happiness is the reward for rational selfishness. Random luck and systemic injustice have no
place in this universe. They are merely
excuses used by the losers to rationalize their failure.
Ethical egoism can serve as a corrective to an ethic of
extreme self-denial and self-sacrifice, but it goes to the opposite extreme of
self-aggrandizement and self-exaltation.
It completely overlooks the interdependence of individuals, the value of
social cohesion, and the role of reciprocity in healthy social relationships.
When Aristotle relegates virtue to a means to the end of
happiness, he acknowledges that individual happiness is dependent, not only on
the individual’s virtue, but on the virtue of others. For Aristotle both virtue and happiness are
socially shared goods. Individual virtue
contributes to the common good, and the common good contributes to individual
happiness. We praise a virtuous character
because it benefits the whole.
So which is better?
To be happy and dishonorable or to be virtuous and unhappy? Ayn Rand would probably choose the former; a strongly religious believer would likely choose the latter. In Aristotle’s world, however, those without
virtue will pay a social price that reduces any happiness and those who are
virtuous will reap a social reward that mitigates any unhappiness.
This ends the series of blog posts since September on
literature and ethics, covering five theories of ethics: authority based divine
command, deontological ethics, relativism, Utilitarianism, and virtue ethics. In practice we use all these theories to one
degree or another. Atheists would not
appeal to the authority of divine command, of course, but they might arrive at
similar values by an appeal to reason.
Likewise, religious adherents, upon finding themselves in an ethical
bind when caught between conflicting divine commands, might have recourse to
independent reason. Different situations
might call for the application of different ethical criteria. This conclusion may sound like relativism,
but reason tells us that relativism, by definition, cannot be absolute. There may be few, if any, ethical absolutes
(rules that apply without exception), but there are surely general ethical principles
(guidelines with sensible exceptions) based on reason and shared human
interests.
One value of literature is that it can dramatize the
abstractions of ethical theory, enabling us to think about it in concrete
terms, bringing to consciousness what we take for granted, raising our
awareness of unanticipated complications, and enhancing our understanding of
what it means to live an ethical life.
No comments:
Post a Comment