I found chapter 9 to be a fascinating discussion of why
people are so attached to their religions as to foreclose any rational
investigation of them.
Daniel Dennett cites three reasons: 1) love that is akin to irrational romance, 2)
the postmodern academic restriction that only sympathizers are qualified to
study religion, and 3) the “belief in belief” discussed earlier (see previous
post Feb., 2014).
First, like lovers who eschew any
rational questioning of their romantic attachments, many religious adherents appeal
to experiences with the divine as beyond words, much less logic. Just as critically analyzing a love
relationship ruins the romance of it, so subjecting the religious experience to
empirical study is completely antithetical to the experience itself, which
transcends all mundane research.
I admit to a certain amount of sympathy
with this line of thought, but when I consider how often irrational romantic
attachment and religious enthusiasm can both lead to destructive, even violent,
behavior, I welcome any study that helps us better understand these states of
mind. And I would think that romantic
lovers and religious believers themselves would want to have some insight into
the difference between a healthy and an unhealthy attachment.
Second, since the advent of postmodern identity politics,
the whole idea of academic neutrality has been thoroughly interrogated and
largely debunked. A male can’t really
study feminism because he is inherently biased in favor of his own gender. The same applies to whites who attempt to
study non-whites or privileged elites who study the poor. Similarly, non-believers cannot escape their
own bias when studying religion and are therefore less credible. It takes a religious sympathizer who applies
academic methods from “inside” the subject matter to arrive at the most
reliable understanding. Of course,
women, non-whites, the less privileged, and religious sympathizers can’t escape
their own biases either, but at least they speak from first-hand
experience.
Again, I see the value of this point of view, but as a white
woman of professional class status I can also see the value of learning about
my social situation from a non-white, non-professional male, who may be able to
instruct me in how my attitudes and behavior affect him. Similarly, as a Unitarian Universalist I think
I can learn from an outside observer of my religious denomination. If absolute objectivity is impossible, then
surely the most complete understanding comes from both an inside and outside
analysis.
Finally, just as Americans who criticize the United States
are sometimes told, “America, love it or leave it!” so those who question
religion, even from within, perhaps especially from within, are often made to
feel like traitors. The “belief in
belief” is so powerful because, just as extreme patriots believe their country
would be better if all its citizens displayed unquestioning loyalty, so
religious adherents often believe that the world would be a better place if
everyone held an unquestioning belief in God.
This last deterrent to the rational study of religion raises
the question of what religion is good for.
Earlier (see previous post Jan., 2014) Dennett had conceded that false
belief can yield benefits, such as greater confidence, optimism, and even enhanced
physical and mental health. In this
chapter he cites empirical studies to support such ameliorative effects of
religion, but he claims the research results are mixed and withholds judgment
until more thorough research can be done.
This certainly seems fair.
At least he does not dismiss the possibility out of hand that religion
may be good for people, regardless of its truth value. Even if the possibility is confirmed, Dennett
raises another question, namely what are the side effects of false belief, and
do they outweigh the benefits? More
importantly, is religion the basis of morality?
And that question will be addressed in the next chapter.
No comments:
Post a Comment